Animals, concepts and contents

Authors

  • Laura Danón Universidad Nacional de Córdoba (UNC)

Keywords:

concepts, propositional contents, animal cognition

Abstract

Nowadays, there is a growing number of philosophers and scientists defending the attribution of intentional mental states to different species of non-human animals. Additionally, these philosophers have usually claimed that, in many cases, those mental sates have propositional contents that represent particular things as being in a certain way. Some of them add to this that, in order to be able to think these contents, it is necessary to have two kinds of concepts: concepts of particulars and concepts of properties. With these ideas in mind, in this paper I will try to answer two questions: What kind of behaviours would provide good evidence that certain non-human animals have concepts of particulars and concepts of properties? And, do we have this kind of evidence? In order to answer these questions, I will firstly examine which cognitive abilities are involved in the possession of concepts of particulars and concepts of properties. Secondly, I will identify several reliable behavioural indicators that an animal has the cognitive capacities required to attribute concepts of particulars and of properties to them. Finally, I will present some empirical examples – the caching strategies of blue-jays and the post-conflict behaviour of chimpanzees— and I will argue that these animals – amongst many others— have both concepts of particulars and of properties. If this is the case, it can be concluded that we also have some reasons to think that there are non-human animals that have mental states with propositional contents, at least in a modest sense.

References

Aguilera, M. (2014). Flexibilidad cognitiva e inferencia. Ludus Vitalis, XII (42): 115-138.

Allen, C. (1999). Animal Concepts Revisited. Erkenntnis, 51 (1), 33-40.

Allen, C. y Bekoff, M. (1997). Species of Mind: The Philosophy and Biology of Cognitive Ethology. Cambridge MA, USA: MIT Press.

Allen, C. & Hauser, M.D. (1991). Concept Attribution in Nonhuman Animals: Theoretical and Methodological Problems in Ascribing Complex Mental Processes. En M.Bekoff y D. Jamieson (Eds.), Readings in Animal Cognition (pp.47-62). Cambridge MA, USA: MIT Press.

Andrews, K. (2015). The Animal Mind. An Introduction to the Philosophy of Animal Cognition. New York, USA: Routledge.

Beck, J. (2012). The Generality Constraint and the Structure of Thought. Mind, 121 (483): 563-600.

Bermúdez, J.L. (2003). Thinking Without Words, New York, USA: Oxford University Press.

Brandom, R. (2000). La articulación de las razones. Madrid, España: Siglo Veintiuno.

Burge, T. (2010). Origins of Objectivity. New York, USA: Oxford University Press.

Camp, E. (2015). Logical Concepts and Associative Characterizations. En E. Margolis y S. Laurence (Eds.), The Conceptual Mind: New Directions in the Study of Concepts (pp. 591-622). Cambridge MA, USA: MIT Press.

Camp, E. (2009). Putting Thoughts to Work: Concepts, Stimulus-Independence and The Generality Constraint. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, LXXVIII (2): 275-31.

Campbell, J. (1995) The Body Image and Self-Consciousness. En J. L.Bermúdez, A. J. Marcel y N.M. Eilan (Eds.), The Body and the Self (29-42). Cambridge MA, USA: The MIT Press.

Carruthers, P. (2004). On Being Simple Minded. American Philosophical Quarterly, 41 (3): 205-220.

Cheney, D. L y Seyfarth, R. (1990). How Monkeys See the World? Inside the Mind of Another Species. Chicago, USA: University of Chicago Press.

Cheney, D. L y Seyfarth, R., (2007). Baboon Metaphysics: The Evolution of a Social Mind. Chicago, USA: University of Chicago Press.

Clayton, N. S. y Dickinson, A. (1998). Episodic-like memory during cache recovery by scrub jays. Nature, 395: 272-278.

Clayton, N, S., Emery, N., y Dickinson, A. (2006). The Rationality of Animal Memory: Complex Caching Strategies of Western Scrub-Jays. En: S. Hurley y M. Nudds (Eds.), Rational Animals (197-216). New York, USA: Oxford University Press.

Cords, M. (1997). Friendships, Alliances, Reciprocity and Repair. En A.Whiten y R.Byrne (Eds.), Machiavellian Intelligence II (24-49). Cambridge, United Kingdom: Cambridge University Press.

Crane, T. (2001). Elements of Mind. New York, USA: Oxford University Press.

Danón, L. (2011). Explicaciones intencionales y explicaciones teleológicas de la conducta animal. Revista Argentina de Ciencias del Comportamiento, 3 (1):54-63.

Davidson, D. (1997). Seeing Through Language. En Truth, Language and History (127-142). New York, USA: Oxford University Press.

Davidson, D. (2001). What Thought Requires. En Problems of Rationality (135-150). New York, USA: Oxford University Press.

De Waal, F. (1989). Peacemaking among Primates. Cambridge MA, USA: Harvard University Press.

Dretske, F. (2000). Perception, Knowledge and Belief. Cambridge, United Kingdom: Cambridge University Press.

Evans, G. (1982). The Varieties of Reference. New York, USA: Oxford University Press.

Glock, H .J. (2000). Animals, Thoughts and Concepts. Synthese, 123 (1): 35-64.

Glock, H.J. (2010a). Concepts, Abilities and Propositions. Grazer Philosophische Studien, 81 (1): 115-134.

Glock, H-J. (2010b). What are Concepts? Conceptus, 39, 7-39.

Glock, H J. (2010c). Can Animals Judge? Dialectica, 64 (1), pp. 11-33.

Grzankowski, A. (2012). Not all Attitudes are Propositional. European Journal of Philosophy, 23 (3): 374-391.

Grzankowski, A. (2013). Non-propositional Attitudes. Philosophy Compass, 8 (12): 1123-1137.

Grzankowski, A. (2016). Attitudes towards Objects. Nous, 50 (2): 314-328

Hutto, D. y Satne, G. (2015) The Natural Origins of Content. Philosophia, 43 (3): 521-536.

Hurley, S. (2003). Animal Action in the Space of Reasons. Mind and Language 18 (3): 231-256.

Lievers, M. (2005). The Structure of Thoughts. En M. Werning, E. Machery y G. Schurz (Eds.), The Compositionality of Meaning and Content, vol. I: Foundational Issues (169-188). Frankfurt, Germany: Ontos Verlag.

Kalpokas, D. (en prensa). Percepción y mentes animales. Revista de Filosofía.

Millikan, R. (2000). On Clear and Confused Ideas. Cambridge, United Kingdom: Cambridge University Press.

Montague, M. (2007). Against Propositionalism. Nous, 41 (3): 503-518

Newen, A. & Bartels, A. (2007). Animal Minds and the Possession of Concepts. Philosophical Psychology, 20 (3): 283-308.

Ristau, C. (1991). Aspects of the Cognitive Ethology of an Injury-feigning Bird, the Pipping-plover. En C. A Ristau (Ed.) Cognitive Ethology: The Minds of Other Animals. Essays in Honor of Donald R. Griffin (91-106). Hillsdale, New Jersey, EE.UU: Laurence Erbaulm Associates.

Proust, J. (2013). The Philosophy of Metacognition. Oxford, United Kingdom: Oxford University Press.

Saidel, E. (2009). Attributing Mental Representations to Animals. En R. Lurz (Ed.), The Philosophy of Animal Minds (35-52). New York, EE.UU: Cambridge University Press.

Sainsbury, M. (2005). Reference without Referents, New York, EE.UU: Oxford University Press.

Strawson, P. (1953). Particular y general. En Ensayos lógico-lingüísticos, Madrid, España: Tecnos.1983.

Strawson, P. (1974). Subject and Predicate in Logic and in Grammar. Aldershot, England: Ashgate Publishing Limited. 2004.

Downloads

Published

2017-12-01

Issue

Section

ARTÍCULOS ECAs

How to Cite

Animals, concepts and contents. (2017). Revista Latinoamericana De Estudios Críticos Animales, 4(2). https://revistaleca.org/index.php/leca/article/view/142